THE UNNECESSARY WAR (WINSTON CHURCHILL: WERE WORLD WAR I AND II NECESSARY AND INEVITABLE?) – WAR: LAW OF WAR, THE EFFECT OF WAR, AND ALTERNATIVES TO WAR TODAY.
INTRODUCTION
What is war?
War
is a complex and multifaceted concept characterized by organized and often
prolonged conflict involving states, nations, or other groups using armed force
to achieve specific political, social, or economic objectives. It is typically distinguished
by intense violence, widespread destruction, and significant human and material
costs. Understanding the nature of war involves exploring its historical,
sociological, political, economic, and psychological dimensions.
There
isn’t a singular definition of war universally accepted across all disciplines.
Instead, various perspectives offer nuanced insights into its nature and
implications. For instance, from a historical standpoint, war has been a
recurrent phenomenon throughout human history. Ancient conflicts, documented in
archaeological findings and historical texts, illustrate the prevalence and
evolution of warfare across civilizations. For example, the works of military
historians like Carl von Clausewitz ("On War") and Thucydides
("History of the Peloponnesian War") provide deep insights into the
nature of conflicts and the factors driving them.
Sociologically,
war is often analyzed in terms of its impact on societies, including changes in
social structures, values, and norms during wartime. The concept of "total
war," introduced during the 20th century, expanded the scope of conflicts
to involve entire societies, affecting civilians and non-combatants
significantly. Sociologists like C. Wright Mills and Emile Durkheim have explored
the societal implications of war in their respective works.
From
a political perspective, war is often seen as a means to achieve strategic
objectives, maintain or alter power relations, or address conflicts of interest
between states or groups. Political scientists and international relations
theorists, such as Kenneth Waltz and Hans Morgenthau, have contributed to the
understanding of war as a tool of statecraft and its impact on global politics.
Moreover,
the economic implications of war cannot be overlooked. Wars have substantial
economic consequences, affecting trade, resources, production, and allocation
of wealth. The works of economists like John Maynard Keynes and Joseph
Schumpeter delve into the economic aspects of war, including its impact on
economies and post-war reconstruction.
Psychologically,
war involves intricate dynamics, including the psychology of warfare, the
effects of combat on individuals, trauma, PTSD (Post-Traumatic Stress
Disorder), and the motivations behind participating in or supporting war
efforts. Psychologists and researchers like Stanley Milgram and Philip Zimbardo
have studied the psychological aspects of conflict and obedience to authority
in wartime situations.
During
this age of instantaneous global media exposure, there's a tendency to presume
a widespread comprehension of this intricate topic. Cicero, the Roman
philosopher and statesman, penned his thoughts on this matter in the 1st
century B.C. defines war as “a contending by force.
Quincy
Wright, an American political scientist and expert in international law,
incorporates the notions of "armed combatants" and
"legality" within his definition of war as a "legal state that
equally authorizes two or more factions to engage in armed conflict." Webster’s
Dictionary defines war as “a state of usually open and declared armed hostile
conflict between states or nations”. Generally, war can be defined as an armed
conflict involving two or more opposing parties, each with significant reasons
motivating their engagement - a description that is admittedly oversimplified.
Law of War
Dr.
Michael Walzer of the Institute of Advanced Study at Princeton discusses law of
war as a comprehensive framework consisting of articulated norms, customs,
professional codes, legal principles, religious and philosophical beliefs, and
reciprocal arrangements when elucidating this concept. For the scope of this
analysis, the ensuing definition will be satisfactory: The law of war comprises
a compilation of unwritten guidelines and formally written regulations originating
from diverse sources, each serving a particular purpose.
The
law of war originates from two separate sources. It draws partly from unwritten
general principles referred to as "customary international law,"
while the specific details of this law stem from a set of codified rules termed
"conventional international law." The unwritten rules are
acknowledged as norms governing the behavior of all nations, while the codified
rules are binding due to explicit consent.
One
source defines customary international law as a set of legal principles
emerging from the "general and consistent practice of States adhered to
due to a sense of legal duty." Another source describes it as the result
of states following a "general and consistent practice driven by the
belief that international law necessitates such conduct." Furthermore,
this source outlines two criteria necessary for a concept to ascend to this
level: the existence of an actual practice or act and the belief by states that
they are bound by a legal obligation. The crucial points to note about this
facet of the law of war are that customary international law primarily
comprises unwritten cultural norms and widely accepted practices, the criteria
of an "act" and a "belief" determine its establishment, and
a state cannot retract its commitment to uphold customary international law.
The
second source, known as conventional international law, encompasses an
extensive compilation of laws, treaties, declarations, and protocols developed
over numerous centuries. It is comparatively simpler to understand than
customary international law but might be more challenging to establish. For
instance, the codified aspect of the law of war comprises explicit laws
governing specific behaviors during armed conflict, necessitating consensus
among an international assembly of legal experts and political figures for
these laws to attain full force under international law. Adding complexity,
this body of legal materials typically evolves in response to global events
that uncover pre-existing deficiencies in codes related to the laws of war only
after such events have occurred.
The
law of war establishes limitations on armed conflict, particularly concerning
the conduct of combatants during action and the treatment of individuals and
entities affected by war, notably those who become victims. Over the course of
history, especially in the last three centuries, a body of written laws has
expanded in response to various global events, particularly conflicts of
varying scales. Among the most widely acknowledged sets of these laws are found
in two categories of treaties - The Hague and Geneva Conventions. The Hague
Conventions comprise two key treaties addressing general hostilities and the
behavior expected from combatants. On the other hand, the Geneva Conventions,
encompassing four distinct conventions and two protocols, focus on protective
measures for civilians and prisoners of war. Notably, the Hague Conventions
recognized the limitations of conventional international law to address or
predict all potential regulatory needs, hence stipulating that in the absence
of relevant treaty laws, civilians and combatants must still adhere to the
protections and restrictions outlined by customary international law.
Purpose of War Regulation
Why
did the evolution of the law of war occur, given that engaging in war is
internationally accepted as a legitimate method of resolving conflicts?
Potentially because inherent in human nature is rationality, prompting
acknowledgment of the necessity to balance military capabilities with long-term
societal harmony as weaponry and tactics advanced. Historian Peter Paret
highlights that writings on war during the 16th and 17th centuries generally
fell into two categories: pioneering works in the realm of international law
and pioneering works detailing advancements in military technology. Before this
period, warfare commonly followed the Machiavellian model advocating
unregulated war, later embodied in what Paret identified as Francis Bacon's
"unapologetic promotion of unrestrained war.
However,
the societal repercussions arising from the Thirty Years' War sparked the
emergence of a group of individuals who opposed the uncontrolled
destructiveness that characterized war on the Continent. Among these figures,
the most prominent was Dutchman Hugo Grotius, who championed an approach
advocating measures to safeguard the rights of private individuals. They
believed that the law of nature encompassed fundamental principles suited to
governing nations, collectively endorsing a central principle described by
Paret as "nations should do to one another the most good in peace, and the
least possible evil in war.
The Purpose of the Law of War
At
its fundamental essence, the law of war serves as the legal framework through which
humanity governs its behavior during times of armed conflict. We've previously
discussed the motivations behind regulating war, and the law of war acts as the
mechanism to achieve those objectives. According to one source, the law of war
endeavors to limit and alleviate the horrors of war, balancing military
necessities with humanity's requirements by distinguishing between permissible
and impermissible actions. Another source asserts that the law of war
integrates humanitarian considerations into warfare (as demonstrated by the
influence of organizations such as the International Committees of the Red
Cross and the Red Crescent) and can function as a strategic advantage. In
essence, the primary purpose of the law of war is to ensure the protection of all
involved parties in a conflict, empower international judicial bodies, regulate
wartime conduct to minimize suffering, and, above all, enable the eventual
restoration of peace.
The Unifying Themes of War
A
law serves one of two objectives: either to prohibit behavior or to manage
behavior. There exist two cohesive themes that collectively form the essence of
the law of war. The initial theme, encapsulated by the term jus
ad bellum, refers to the legal and philosophical aspects of the law of
war aimed at averting armed conflicts and, in cases where prevention fails,
defining the circumstances under which war should be initiated. The second
theme, designated by the term jus in bello, pertains to the
components of the law of war designed to govern or manage the actions of combatants
involved in armed conflict - it delineates the principles guiding the conduct
of warfare.
The
concept of Jus ad bellum predates the other theme. It delineates the
conditions that validate the legal and moral justifications for utilizing
military force. Early societies directed their concerns regarding armed
conflicts toward formulating guidelines for the rightful application of force
and dedicated minimal intellectual attention to controlling the implementation
of such force. There was a widespread acceptance that if armed conflict was
deemed legally justified, limitations on its application were deemed
unnecessary. This progression prompts the inquiry: What precisely constitutes a
"just war"?
Throughout
history, the tradition of a "just
war," encompassing a set of mutually accepted rules governing combat,
tends to develop commonly between culturally akin adversaries. In situations
where two warring groups share a range of common values, it's frequently
observed that they implicitly or explicitly establish boundaries for their
warfare. Conversely, when opposing factions significantly differ due to varying
religious beliefs, ethnicity, or language, perceiving each other as
fundamentally distinct or inferior, adherence to war conventions becomes
infrequent. Only when adversaries perceive one another as a unified group,
sharing a moral identity and with whom they anticipate future peaceful
interactions, do they formulate implicit or explicit regulations concerning the
conduct of wars. This formulation includes considerations about who should
participate, how wars should be conducted, and the nature of relations
post-war. In part, the motivation behind establishing or agreeing to these
conventions can be seen as mutually advantageous—preferred over resorting to
deceitful tactics or weaponry that might instigate an endless cycle of
retaliatory actions or actions that have previously proven detrimental to the
political or moral interests of both sides.
In
the 1st century B.C., Cicero articulated that a state should only engage in war
when defending its honor or safety. Additionally, he outlined specific
conditions that needed to be met for a war to be justified: proper declaration
by authorities, notifying the opponent of the declaration, and offering a
chance for peaceful negotiation before conflict ensued. This endeavor to
establish criteria for justification likely marked the initial formal effort,
particularly in the Western context, to create a universally acknowledged
method of commencing war—essentially, the early foundations of jus
ad bellum.
As
Empire expanded, the rationale for justifying war became increasingly intricate
and subject to differing interpretations. This led the burgeoning Christian
Church to reassess its pacifist stance, considering the practical necessities
of survival against invading groups like the barbarians. Consequently, early
Christian scholars such as Saint Augustine and Saint Thomas Aquinas endeavored
to harmonize church teachings with pragmatic politics by replacing the Roman
legal standards for justifying war with a moral or religious standpoint. They
framed a perspective where the forces of good battled against evil, seeking
God's blessing for the Empire's necessary wars for survival. This resulting
doctrine of just war progressed into the initial of the two themes within the
law of war.
Over
twelve centuries following the collapse of the Western Roman Empire, the
influence of theologians from the church pervaded all facets of Western
society, including political theory. Saint Augustine, in the 5th century,
merged the Roman viewpoint on just war with emerging Christian beliefs and the
pragmatic reality of survival. He ultimately developed a political theory
regarding just war, with a religious perspective intertwined.
Acknowledging
Cicero's definition of a just war as one that sought retribution for an affront
to honor or property, Augustine also recognized the three Roman principles of
just war: a legitimate cause, declaration by proper authority, and the
objective of peace. However, Augustine attributed one fundamental purpose to
war: it was the means through which God either punished humanity or absolved
them of sins. From this standpoint, Augustine posited that any war ordained by
God was inherently just. Following this line of thought, it logically followed
(from a Western viewpoint) that war was an acceptable instrument of God's will.
Therefore, any state leader could morally justify declaring war if it was
construed as supporting God's will, however broadly interpreted.
This
shift in approach, from an objective Roman perspective to a morality-centered
view, was a fusion of early political philosophy and Christian theology's
concepts of good and evil. This fusion remained largely unaltered until the
mid-13th century. As just-war theorist Paul Christopher noted, Beginning with
Augustine, war... became more than just a legal remedy for injustice; it became
a moral imperative. This morality-centric approach to jus ad bellum, markedly
distinct from the Romans' objective outlook, represented a synthesis of early
political thought and Christian theology, and endured until later centuries.
Aquinas
made a notable contribution to jus ad bellum theory by extensively
presenting secular examples and analyzing each category of justification. His
stipulation that a just war must be declared by the appropriate authority
reflects ancient Roman practices. However, Aquinas redefines proper authority
as an entity not subject to higher secular levels. In a subsequent study, he
broadens the definition of just cause" to encompass actions taken to
avenge wrongs, penalize a state for refusing to make amends for these wrongs,
and restore unlawfully seized property. The third and final characteristic of a
just war, according to Aquinas, involves conducting the war with the
"right intentions," which include motives such as promoting good,
ensuring peace, punishing evil, and avoiding further wrongdoing. Notably,
Aquinas asserts that a war adhering to the first two characteristics (declared
by proper authority and fought for a just cause) could still be considered
unjust if not prosecuted with the right intentions. His work amalgamated the
ideologies of Greek and Roman philosophers and early church theologians,
amalgamating these with the pragmatic political stance prevalent in medieval
Europe. Aquinas' codification of these three jus ad bellum principles persisted
for 300 years, laying the groundwork for the subsequent influential law-of-war
theorist, Hugo Grotius.
Hugo
Grotius, perhaps second only to Dr. Francis Lieber, wielded a profound
influence on the evolution of the law of war. To grasp the magnitude of
Grotius' impact on the law of war overall, and specifically on jus ad bellum,
understanding the context of the early 17th-century Europe in which he lived,
studied, and wrote is crucial—an environment shaped by the devastation of the
Thirty Years War.
Hugo
Grotius, a jurist and humanist of the 17th century, gained global recognition
following his victorious handling of a significant legal dispute involving the
seizure of a Portuguese merchant ship by Holland. This high-profile case,
coupled with the extensive research he conducted to support his argument,
propelled him toward further exploration in the realm of international law.
Grotius had already developed an interest in this field due to his observations
during the Thirty Years War. He is most renowned for encapsulating his views on
international law in the three-volume work titled "De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri
Tres" (The Law of War and Peace). In the prologue of this
influential work, he characterizes the Europe of his era with these words:
“Throughout the Christian world I observed a lack of
restraint in relations to war, such as even barbarous races should be ashamed
of; I observed that men rush to arms for slight causes, or no cause at all, and
that when arms have once been taken up there is no longer any respect for law,
divine or human; it is as if, in accordance with a general decree, frenzy had
openly been let loose for the committing of all crimes”
Grotius
expanded upon the three previously discussed just-war principles (declaration
by legitimate authority, fighting for a just cause, and fighting with right
intentions) by introducing five additional elements. Understanding the context
of his era and the impact of the Thirty Years War clarifies that his primary
aim was to prevent war whenever feasible, or at the very least, to mitigate its
societal impact. These supplementary principles included:
1. War
must consider proportionality, ensuring that the war's ultimate goal aligns
proportionally with the societal impact or damage the war may cause.
2. War
should be pursued with a reasonable likelihood of success.
3. War
ought to be publicly declared.
4. War
should only be employed as a last resort.
5. War
must be conducted justly.
Grotius'
influence on the development of jus ad bellum was substantial due to
his perspective grounded in natural law, advocating limitations on rulers and
states. Significantly, his proposition that natural law held sway over all
individuals and communities elevated it above canonical law. Consequently, when
Grotius' principles were articulated in The Law of War and Peace, secular
leaders across Europe promptly acknowledged them as the most suitable
guidelines for conducting warfare in international diplomacy on the Continent.
By substituting church influence with a code rooted in natural law, Grotius
aimed to eradicate the prospect of wars waged solely for religious reasons.
Wars remained possible but were now subject to a more objective checklist for
justification, open to international scrutiny. This compilation of eight jus ad
bellum principles, along with the identification of four legitimate causes for
waging a just war (defense, repossession of property, recovery of debts, and
punishment), has steered the international community for over 375 years and
generally aligns with customary international law. Nevertheless, a
comprehensive analysis of the law of war necessitates a discussion of its
second unifying theme, the regulation of wartime conduct, typically encompassed
in conventional international law referred to as jus in bello.
Grotius
proposed three inquiries designed to function as regulatory guidelines for jus
in bello: identifying who could be lawfully targeted, determining the
permissible means of engagement, and establishing standards for the treatment
of prisoners. These guiding principles continued to develop over the subsequent
four centuries. For instance, in 1863, Dr. Francis Lieber referred to
"justice," "faith," and "honor" in his
Instructions for the Government of Armies of the United States in the Field.
During World War I, a US Army publication on the law of war advocated the
application of "necessity," "humanity," and
"chivalry" in combat. Present-day law-of-war doctrine acknowledges
the significance of three fundamental principles—"discrimination,"
"proportionality," and "responsibility"—as the cornerstone
upon which combatants must base their actions.
Causes of war
In
its essence, war intensifies, leading to a series of actions and reactions,
each countered by a stronger response until one of the parties involved is
depleted. The impact of war significantly burdens the economy and society of
the nations at war, often causing irreversible transformations in their culture
and profoundly influencing their political landscape for extended periods. As
famously articulated by Clausewitz:
War
is always a serious means for a serious object….Such is War, such the Commander
who conducts it; such the theory which rules it. But War is not pastime; no
mere passion for venturing and winning; no work of a free enthusiasm: it is a
serious means for a serious object (Clausewitz et al, 2008, pg. 30).
War
stems from inherent human traits and behaviors, encompassing a range of
psychological factors, emotions, and inherent characteristics that constitute
the core human experience. Among the fundamental traits shared universally
among humans across societies are our imperfections and the inherent
differences that have shaped cultural norms throughout history. Although humans
are not inherently predisposed towards war and destruction, conflicts arise as
a result of envy, selfishness, and the instinct for self-preservation. Kenneth
Waltz, in his analysis of "the first image" in "Man, the State,
and War," contends that all "other causes are secondary,"
highlighting that the passions leading to war already exist latent within a
society (Clausewitz et al., 2008, p. 33).
Another
common human trait is the inherent need for security, succinctly explained by
Maslow's hierarchy of needs. Maslow posits that when physiological needs are
reasonably fulfilled, a new set of needs emerges, categorized as the safety
needs (Maslow, 1943, p. 6). Additionally, Liberty Hobbes observed that
"everyone in a state of nature fears for his safety, and each is out to
injure the other before he is injured himself" (Waltz, 2001, p. 93). In the
realm of international relations, theoretical frameworks often refer to this
need for safety among societal groups as the concept of security.
Security
closely aligns with the subjective perception of safety within a particular
societal group. Arnold Wolfers defines security as "the absence of threats
to acquire values objectively, while subjectively, it is the absence of fear
that such values will be attacked" (Baylis et al., 2017, p. 240). Although
state power and military capability may quantify security, it primarily
manifests as a feeling—a lack of threat-induced anxiety—on an individual level.
Despite
various causes of conflict, human beings often justify their actions based on
the belief that their morality is superior, a notion that has perpetuated
conflicts throughout history. St. Augustine of Hippo set a precedent for
justifying violence in pursuit of the "common good," a concept based
on societal norms. The commonly embraced just war tradition asserts that any
conflict aimed at achieving a state of peace is acceptable, guided by the
principles of jus ad bellum, Jus in bello, and jus
post bellum, each incorporating varying levels of subjectivity (Baylis
et al., 2017, p. 215).
Acknowledging
that the fundamental need for safety ingrained in human nature extends to the
state, compelling a drive for security competition manifested in weaponry
advancements, preemptive measures, and power equilibrium to ensure the state's
ideological continuity, enables us to delve deeper into the repercussions of
this conflict. However, the underlying motives behind these actions often
differ significantly from the primary pursuit of security. Throughout history,
conflicts have typically centered on societies or groups seeking to impose
their beliefs on others, pursue economic or territorial advantages, or strive
for independence. We will particularly examine the factors of economic gain and
territorial expansion, preemptive military actions, religious convictions,
internal strife, revolutionary movements, and.
Economic Gain and Territorial
Expansion
Historically,
the quest for territory and resources has stood out as one of the primary
ancillary causes behind conflicts. The acquisition of land and the accompanying
resources directly contribute to a state's power, subsequently bolstering the
security of the invading state. This sentiment is encapsulated in the
Athenians' message to the Melians as recorded in Thucydides' "History of
the Peloponnesian War," where they assert, besides extending our empire we
should gain in security by your subjection, highlighting the belief that
territorial expansion and the subjugation of other groups are perceived as
means to enhance security (Thucydides, 1810, p. 389).
A
contemporary illustration of this would be Russia, which has engaged in
unlawful annexations in both Ukraine and Georgia, primarily aiming to expand
its territory. In relation to this instance, Waltz comments:
An explanation may be made in terms of geographic or
economic deprecations or in terms of deprivations too vaguely defined to be
labeled at all. Thus a nation may argue that it has not attained it “natural”
frontiers, that such frontiers are necessary to its security, that war to
extend the state to its deserved compass is justified or even necessary (Waltz,
2001, pg. 91).
Preemptive Military Actions
A
scenario that often accelerates conflict prematurely involves the concept of
preemptive warfare. Even if a state aims to maintain peace, it might find
itself compelled to contemplate engaging in a preventive war. Faced with the
possibility that failure to strike at an opportune moment might lead to being
targeted later when the advantage shifts to the opposing side (Waltz, 2001, p. 21).
Sun Tzu once articulated, he will win who, prepared himself, waits to take the
enemy unprepared. He will win who has the military capacity and is not
interfered with by the sovereign" (Tzu, 1910, pg. 68). Military
strategists understand the pivotal importance of seizing the initiative and
sustaining momentum and boldness in offensive actions, often translating such
strategies to the state level, where, in the pursuit of security, a state opts
for preemptive strikes.
Internal Strife
Marxists,
drawing insights from Carl Marx's manifesto, frequently emphasize internal
conflicts such as civil wars as catalysts for state violence. While their
analyses primarily center on class tensions, it is not uncommon for states to
grapple with ideological disparities within their territorial boundaries,
prompting efforts to establish dominance or incite revolutions through force.
The United States' own Revolutionary War serves as a prominent example, seeking
independence from Great Britain on the grounds of "no taxation without
representation." For the United States to forge its democracy and institute
a stable society aligned with its principles, escalating conflict to the point
of war was necessary to attain independence.
Even
post a successful revolution or resolution of civil strife, the remnants of
ideologies may persist, lying dormant within society and potentially leading to
future conflicts. Clausewitz noted, even the ultimate outcome of an entire War
may not always be perceived as absolute. The defeated state often perceives it
merely as a temporary setback, reparable in the future (Clausewitz et al, 2008,
pg. 20).
Religious Convictions
Throughout
history, war has been instrumental in determining the dominance of particular
ideologies. Some of the most intense conflicts have been rooted in religious
ideologies. The belief in the promise of a specific afterlife has motivated
various groups to escalate and validate conflicts in the pursuit of their
ideologies for millennia. The ultimate objective of many of these groups is to
establish a secure and stable society that adheres to their chosen religion.
Similar to governance, they seek security to ensure stability. The medieval
crusades from the 10th to the 12th centuries represent a widely recognized
instance of religious conflict. Nonetheless, even in contemporary times,
religious conflicts persist worldwide.
An
evident example of religiously driven conflict lies in the enduring presence of
Islamic extremism in the Middle East, propagated by violent non-state actors.
Numerous radical Muslims aspire to establish a society centered on a purified
form of Islam, striving to return to the Islam practiced and preached by
Mohammed in the early 7th century, seeking to recapture the divine blessings
enjoyed by early believers (Suarez, 2013, pg. 14). In the present era, these
extremists repeatedly demonstrate their readiness to resort to violence in
pursuit of this religious objective.
The Effects of War
The
effects of war are multifaceted and can profoundly impact various aspects of
society, including human lives, economies, infrastructure, and cultures. Here
is an analysis of some significant effects of war along with concrete examples:
1) Loss of Lives and Injuries:
War leads to significant casualties and injuries among civilians and military
personnel. The loss of life and physical harm are among the most devastating
consequences. For instance, the Syrian Civil War, ongoing since 2011, has
resulted in hundreds of thousands of deaths and millions of people being
injured or displaced (UNHCR, 2021). The conflict between Israel and Palestine
has led to significant human suffering. According to various reports, including
those from Amnesty International ("Israel and Occupied Palestinian
Territories"), the conflict has resulted in the loss of thousands of
lives, including civilians, children, and combatants, causing trauma and
emotional distress among the affected populations. The constant threat of
violence, displacement, and loss of livelihoods has had long-lasting
psychological effects on individuals and communities on both sides.
2) Destruction of Infrastructure:
Wars often result in the destruction of critical infrastructure, including
homes, hospitals, schools, and transportation systems. The bombing campaigns
during World War II led to the extensive destruction of cities like Dresden,
Germany, and Tokyo, Japan, causing immense damage to buildings and
infrastructure.
3) Displacement and Refugees:
Wars force people to flee their homes, leading to mass displacement and
creating refugee crises. The ongoing conflict in Afghanistan has resulted in
millions of Afghans seeking refuge in neighboring countries and beyond,
contributing to one of the world's largest refugee populations (UNHCR, 2021).
4) Economic Consequences:
Wars have significant economic repercussions, causing disruptions to trade,
commerce, and industries. They drain government resources, diverting funds from
social welfare and development projects. The Gulf War in 1990-1991 had a severe
impact on Iraq's economy due to sanctions and destruction of infrastructure
(World Bank, n.d.).
5) Psychological and Social Impact:
War leaves a lasting impact on the mental health of individuals and
communities. PTSD, depression, anxiety, and trauma are widespread among war
survivors. For example, the Rwandan Genocide in 1994 resulted in long-term
psychological scars among survivors, leading to widespread trauma and
psychological issues (WHO, 2021).
6) Cultural and Social Disruption:
Wars can disrupt cultural heritage, erasing historical sites, artifacts, and
traditions. The destruction of ancient monuments and artifacts during the
Syrian Civil War, such as the ancient city of Palmyra, has resulted in the loss
of invaluable cultural heritage (UNESCO, 2021).
The Unnecessary War (Winston
Churchill: were World War I and II necessary and inevitable?) is there an
alternative to war today?
In
this extensive and thought-provoking historical account, Patrick Buchanan
argues that had it not been for the errors made by British statesmen,
particularly Winston Churchill, the devastating events of two world wars and
the Holocaust could have been averted, and the downfall of the British Empire
might not have occurred. The grim era of oppressive Communist rule, causing
immense suffering to millions for half a century, might have been prevented,
allowing Europe to maintain its central role in global affairs for generations
to come.
World War I
Regarding
World War I, Buchanan contends that Britain initially had no conflict with
Germany before 1914. However, the considerable expansion of the Imperial German
Navy, led by Admiral Alfred von Tirpitz, was perceived as a "threat to
Britain." Consequently, the British redirected the majority of their Royal
Navy to European waters and formed alliances with Russia and France. Buchanan
argues that this strategic shift, tying England closely to Europe, was a
disastrous policy that ultimately led Britain to be entangled in the war.
On
another note, Buchanan attributes a significant portion of the deteriorating
Anglo-German relations to the "Germanophobia" and the fervent pursuit
of the Entente Cordiale with France by British Foreign Secretary Edward Grey.
When evaluating the responsibility for the unfolding events, Buchanan suggests
that Britain could have easily halted the Anglo-German naval arms race in 1912
by committing to neutrality in a conflict between Germany and France.
Buchanan
challenges the notion of "Prussian militarism" as an anti-German
fabrication by certain British statesmen. According to him, Germany's
historical record supports the idea that it was the least militaristic among
the European Powers. Buchanan emphasizes that until 1914, German Kaiser Wilhelm
II had not engaged in any war, contrasting this with Winston Churchill's
involvement in three wars, stating that Churchill had more firsthand war
experience than almost any soldier in the German army.
In
terms of the outbreak of war in 1914, Buchanan contends that Wilhelm was eager
to avoid conflict and accepts the German assertion that Russian mobilization on
July 31 forced Germany into war. He accuses Churchill and Grey of committing
Britain to enter the war by making promises to defend France without the
knowledge of the Cabinet or Parliament.
Buchanan
criticizes the British "hunger blockade" of Germany during World War
I as "criminal" and aligns with the argument presented by British economist
John Maynard Keynes. Keynes, in his 1919 work "The Economic Consequences
of the Peace," asserted that the reparations imposed on Germany in the
Treaty of Versailles were "impossible" to fulfill.
World War II
Buchanan
puts forth the hypothesis that the harsh terms of the Treaty of Versailles
played a pivotal role in triggering World War II. He contends that the treaty,
perceived as unjust towards Germany, justified German attempts to revise it,
characterizing these efforts as both moral and just. The aftermath of the
Treaty's imposition, according to Buchanan, fueled German nationalism, paving
the way for the rise of Adolf Hitler. In Buchanan's perspective, Britain,
France, Italy, and Czechoslovakia indirectly contributed to Hitler's ascent to
power in 1933.
According
to Buchanan, leaders in Weimar-era Germany, such as Gustav Stresemann, Heinrich
Brüning, and Friedrich Ebert, were responsible statesmen working to revise
Versailles without threatening European peace. However, their efforts were
hampered by the reluctance of Britain and France to cooperate. Buchanan
contends that Hitler's foreign policy, when he assumed power in 1933, was more
moderate than the war aims outlined by German Chancellor Theobald von Bethmann
Hollweg in the Septemberprogramm
during World War I. Buchanan argues that Hitler's territorial aspirations were
focused on Eastern Europe and did not extend to Western Europe and Africa.
Buchanan
suggests that Hitler perceived the Franco-Soviet Pact as a threat, arguing that
it violated the Locarno Treaties, and used this claim as a diplomatic weapon
against which the French and British had no effective response. According to
Buchanan, Hitler's demands on Poland in 1938 and 1939 were an attempt to build
an anti-Soviet German-Polish alliance. He argues that Hitler wanted Poland as
an ally, not an enemy.
Buchanan
agrees with British historian E. H. Carr's view that the use of force to
maintain the status quo might be morally more culpable than altering it. He
maintains that Hitler did not desire a war with Britain and criticizes
Britain's decision to declare war in 1939.
Buchanan
criticizes the Morgenthau Plan of 1944 as a genocidal proposal promoted by
Henry Morgenthau and his deputy, Soviet agent Harry Dexter White, to ensure
Soviet dominance in Europe. He accuses Churchill of accepting this plan
amorally.
Regarding
the Holocaust, Buchanan argues that its scale would not have reached the same
magnitude without Hitler's invasion of Poland and the Soviet Union. He suggests
that if Churchill had accepted Hitler's peace offer in 1940, the severity of
the Holocaust might have been significantly reduced.
Buchanan
endorses the concept of Western betrayal, accusing Churchill and Roosevelt of
handing over Eastern Europe to the Soviet Union at the Tehran Conference and
the Yalta Conference. He asserts that the United States should have stayed out
of World War II, blaming Churchill for pressuring the British Cabinet in 1921
to end its alliance with Japan, ultimately leading to Japan aligning with the
Axis and attacking Pearl Harbor.
In
his conclusion, Buchanan critiques former President George W. Bush, drawing
parallels between Churchill's involvement in unnecessary wars and Bush's
actions in Iraq. Buchanan contends that Bush, influenced by Churchill's
neoconservative foreign policy, led the United States into ruin by making
commitments to numerous nations without vital interests, reminiscent of
Churchill's wartime decisions.
Alternatives to war
Is
there an alternative to war today?
Yes,
there are several alternatives to war in contemporary international relations.
These alternatives focus on diplomacy, conflict resolution, and collaboration
to address disputes and conflicts. Here are some extensive explanations with
concrete examples:
1.
Diplomacy
and Negotiation
Diplomacy
involves the use of dialogue, negotiations, and communication to resolve
conflicts between nations without resorting to armed conflict. Skilled
diplomats work to find common ground, build understanding, and reach
agreements. For instance, the Iran Nuclear Deal (Joint Comprehensive Plan of
Action or JCPOA) in 2015 is an example of successful diplomacy. Through
negotiations involving multiple countries, including the United States, Iran
agreed to limit its nuclear program in exchange for the lifting of economic
sanctions.
2.
International
Mediation and Conflict Resolution
This
involves impartial third parties or international organizations facilitating
discussions between conflicting parties to find mutually acceptable solutions. Example
is The Oslo Accords in the 1990s, mediated by Norway, brought Israelis and
Palestinians to the negotiating table, resulting in agreements aimed at
resolving the Israeli-Palestinian conflict.
3.
International
Organizations and Treaties
International
bodies and treaties provide frameworks for cooperation and conflict resolution,
promoting adherence to established norms and rules. The United Nations (UN)
plays a crucial role in conflict prevention and resolution. UN peacekeeping
missions, such as those in Cyprus and Lebanon, aim to maintain peace and
stability.
4.
Economic
Sanctions
Imposing
economic sanctions can be a way to influence a nation's behavior without
resorting to military action. Sanctions can be designed to pressure governments
to change policies or comply with international norms. For instance, the
sanctions imposed on South Africa during the apartheid era contributed to the
dismantling of the discriminatory system by putting economic pressure on the
government.
5.
Crisis
Prevention and Early Warning Systems
Utilizing
intelligence, monitoring, and analysis to identify potential conflicts early
on, allowing for preventive measures to be taken. The European Union's Conflict Early Warning
System (EWS) for instance, monitors
regions of potential concern, providing policymakers with information to
address issues before they escalate into armed conflicts.
6.
Cultural
Exchange and Public Diplomacy
Promoting
mutual understanding and cultural exchange to build positive relationships and
reduce misunderstandings. Programs like the Fulbright Scholar Program foster
cultural exchange by sending scholars and students between countries, fostering
cross-cultural understanding and collaboration.
7.
Technology
for Conflict Prevention
The
use of technology for surveillance and early warning systems as well as, communication
to prevent conflicts from escalating. The use of satellite imagery and social
media analysis can provide real-time information about potential conflict zones,
helping international actors respond proactively.
8.
International
Law and Human Rights Advocacy
Emphasizing
the importance of international law and human rights standards to address
grievances and hold nations accountable for their actions. The International
Criminal Court (ICC) prosecutes individuals for genocide, war crimes, and
crimes against humanity, providing a legal avenue for addressing atrocities.
In
today's interconnected world, a combination of these alternatives is often
employed to address conflicts and promote peace, emphasizing the importance of
dialogue, cooperation, and international collaboration.
References
Amnesty
International. (2021). Israel and Occupied Palestinian Territories. Retrieved
from https://www.amnesty.org/en/countries/middle-east-and-north-africa/israel-and-occupied- palestinian-territories/
Baylis,
J., Owens, P., Smith, S. (2017). The globalization of world politics:
An introduction
to international relations. New
York, NY: Oxford University Press. 7th edition.
Print.
Buchanan, Patrick 'Pat' Joseph (May 27,
2008), Churchill,
Hitler, and The Unnecessary War: How
Britain Lost Its Empire and the West Lost the World, New York: Crown, ISBN 978-0-307-40515-9.
Clausewitz, Carl von.
1997. On War. Translated by J. J.
Graham. Wordsworth Classics of World
Literature. Ware, England: Wordsworth Editions.
Durkheim, Emile 1933 The Division of Labor in Society.
(1893) George Simpson, trans. New York:
Macmillan.
Hugo
Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, Libre Tres, trans. Francis W. Kelsey (London:
Wildy & Sons Ltd, 1964), 33;
hereafter referred to as Grotius.
John M. K. The Economic Consequences of
the Peace. (New York: Harcourt, Brace and Howe. 1920. Pp. 298.)
Lieber,
Dr. Francis. General Orders Number 100: Instructions for the Government of the
Armies for the United States in the
Field. Washington, DC: Adjutant General’s Office, 1863.
Marx,
K., Engels, F., & Likes, S. (2012). The communist manifesto
(Rethinking the western tradition) (J
Isaac, Ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press. eBook.
Maslow,
A. H., (1943). A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review,
50(4), 370-396. doi:10.1037/h0054346.
Milgram, S. (1974) Obedience to authority: An
experimental view. Tavistock, London.
Mills, C.W. (1959) The Sociological
Imagination. Oxford University Press, New York.
Morgenthau, H. J. (1948). Politics among
nations. The struggle for power and peace. New York, Knopf.
Paret,
Peter. Makers of Modern Strategy from Machiavelli to the Nuclear Age.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1986.
Suarez-Murias,
A. (2013). "Jihad is the way and death for the sake of allah is
our highest aspiration": A
narrative analysis of sayyid qutb's milestones. Retrieved from https://wakespace.lib.wfu.edu/handle/10339/38576.
Thucydides. 1963. History of the Peloponnesian War. Translated by Rex Warner.
Penguin Classics. London,
England: Penguin Classics.
Tzu,
S., Evans, M., & Giles, L. (2017). The art of war. (Knicker
bocker classics). Laguna Hills: Race
Point Publishing.
United
Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). (2021).
Syrian Cultural Heritage. Retrieved
from https://whc.unesco.org/en/syrianculturalheritage/
United
Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR). (2021). Global Trends: Forced Displacement in 2020. Retrieved from
https://www.unhcr.org/globaltrends2020/
Waltz, K. (1979). Theory of international politics.
Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Waltz,
Kenneth. (2001). Man, the state, and war: A theoretical analysis.
New York: Columbia University Press.
eBook.
Walzer,
Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations.
New York: Harper Collins, 1977.
World
Bank. (n.d.). The Economic and Social Impact of the Gulf War. Retrieved from https://openknowledge.worldbank.org/handle/10986/29379
World
Health Organization (WHO). (2021). Mental Health Consequences of Disasters. Retrieved from https://www.who.int/health-topics/disasters#tab=tab_1
Zimbardo, P. (2007). The Lucifer
effect: Understanding how good people turn evil. Random House.
Comments
Post a Comment